UNIVERSAL TURING MACHINE: Difference between revisions
(Created page with "==UNIVERSAL TURING MACHINE== ANNOTATION |...| John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 pp.70-73 Turing's 1936 paper...") |
No edit summary |
||
(14 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
= | <p class="pt-link">[[Play Like an Idiot#UNIVERSAL_TURING_MACHINE|Play Like an Idiot]]</p> | ||
<p class="parallel-text"> | |||
The architecture of John Von Neumann and Warren McCulloch's "logic machine" was established in 1936 by Alan Turing's theoretical Universal Machine, which. like SEER, is a finite state machine.<br> | |||
ANNOTATION<br> | |||
|...| John Johnston, ''The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI'', MIT, 2008<br> | |||
pp.70-73<br> | |||
<br> | |||
<br> | |||
Turing's 1936 paper on the Universal Machine was instrumental in arriving at a new understanding of a real-abstract machine. The Turing Machine: comprises three parts: | |||
</p> | |||
<p class="parallel-indent"> | |||
1) a reading/writing "head"<br> | |||
2) an infinitely long "tape" divided into squares which pass along the head<br> | |||
3) a table of instructions (state transition table) which would tell the head what to do in relation to the machine's state. It would ask: is the mark absent or present on the tape? | |||
</p> | |||
<p class="parallel-text"> | |||
Depending on the outcome the machine encounters, it would:</p> | |||
<p class="parallel-indent"> | |||
a) enter a mark<br> | |||
b) erase a mark<br> | |||
c) leave the square blank <ref> John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 p.70</ref><br> | |||
</p> | |||
<p class="parallel-text"> | |||
The Turing Machine is the first example of a finite state machine. Data entering as a string of symbols (1 or 0) are encoded as absent or present. | The Turing Machine is the first example of a finite state machine. Data entering as a string of symbols (1 or 0) are encoded as absent or present. | ||
Instructions: If no mark = (state 1) enter mark, move to square on left = (state 2); if there is a mark move to square on the right and remain in state 2. | Instructions: If no mark = (state 1) enter mark, move to square on left = (state 2); if there is a mark move to square on the right and remain in state 2. | ||
The tape serves as a memory. Turing's thesis was that “every computation expressible as an algorithm, or every determinate procedure in a formal system, has its equivalent in a universal computing machine (aka Universal Turing Machine)” <ref> John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 p.70</ref> | The tape serves as a memory. Turing's thesis was that “every computation expressible as an algorithm, or every determinate procedure in a formal system, has its equivalent in a universal computing machine (aka Universal Turing Machine)” <ref> John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 p.70</ref><br> | ||
To return directly to Lacan and Seminar II, this universality makes it a new kind of machine which is defined by a logic or function rather than a material structure. | To return directly to Lacan and Seminar II, this universality makes it a new kind of machine which is defined by a logic or function rather than a material structure.<br> | ||
This, Lacan suggests, is a characteristic which such machines and humans share. But humans also have access to the imaginary-symbolic] a logical form which is given equivalence in a set of algorithms. A number of machines, from ENIAC (1946) to UNIVAC (1946) were automated, self-regulating arbitrary symbols combine to rules of composition – syntax, to produce more complex operations. Johnston: "This behaviour is used to physically instantiate a symbol system with its own independent rules or syntax." <ref> John Johnston, ''The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI'', MIT, 2008 p.71</ref> In this way thinking machines automating the “laws of thought” unlike any previous machine. | |||
This, Lacan suggests, is a characteristic which such machines and humans share. But humans also have access to the imaginary-symbolic] a logical form which is given equivalence in a set of algorithms. | </p> | ||
[[Category:Parallel Text]] | [[Category:Parallel Text]] |
Latest revision as of 12:49, 15 March 2021
The architecture of John Von Neumann and Warren McCulloch's "logic machine" was established in 1936 by Alan Turing's theoretical Universal Machine, which. like SEER, is a finite state machine.
ANNOTATION
|...| John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008
pp.70-73
Turing's 1936 paper on the Universal Machine was instrumental in arriving at a new understanding of a real-abstract machine. The Turing Machine: comprises three parts:
1) a reading/writing "head"
2) an infinitely long "tape" divided into squares which pass along the head
3) a table of instructions (state transition table) which would tell the head what to do in relation to the machine's state. It would ask: is the mark absent or present on the tape?
Depending on the outcome the machine encounters, it would:
a) enter a mark
b) erase a mark
c) leave the square blank [1]
The Turing Machine is the first example of a finite state machine. Data entering as a string of symbols (1 or 0) are encoded as absent or present.
Instructions: If no mark = (state 1) enter mark, move to square on left = (state 2); if there is a mark move to square on the right and remain in state 2.
The tape serves as a memory. Turing's thesis was that “every computation expressible as an algorithm, or every determinate procedure in a formal system, has its equivalent in a universal computing machine (aka Universal Turing Machine)” [2]
To return directly to Lacan and Seminar II, this universality makes it a new kind of machine which is defined by a logic or function rather than a material structure.
This, Lacan suggests, is a characteristic which such machines and humans share. But humans also have access to the imaginary-symbolic] a logical form which is given equivalence in a set of algorithms. A number of machines, from ENIAC (1946) to UNIVAC (1946) were automated, self-regulating arbitrary symbols combine to rules of composition – syntax, to produce more complex operations. Johnston: "This behaviour is used to physically instantiate a symbol system with its own independent rules or syntax." [3] In this way thinking machines automating the “laws of thought” unlike any previous machine.
- ↑ John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 p.70
- ↑ John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 p.70
- ↑ John Johnston, The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI, MIT, 2008 p.71